📜 ⬆️ ⬇️

On the way to the physical principles of biological evolution. Finish + full translation

Abridged translation of the article by M. Katsnelson, Y. Wolf and E. Kunin
Towards physical principles of biological evolution
Mikhail I. Katsnelson, Yuri I. Wolf, Eugene V. Koonin
Original article
(The two previous parts have already been published: the beginning and the continuation )

Is convergence of physics and biology possible?


An article suggestive of such reflections, I became interested in the presentation of the astrophysicist and popularizer of science Sergei Popov. In one of his reviews of preprints, an article with an intriguing title was mentioned, and among the authors was Yevgeny Kunin. I began to read the book of this author, The Logic of Case ... Of course, only separate sections. Engineering education, doing technical translations, reading popular science articles - all this brought me to a seditious thought - to perform a brief translation of an article written by Yevgeny Kunin in collaboration with Mikhail Katsnelson and Yury Wolf.

annotation


Biological systems achieve complex organization, which significantly exceeds the complexity of any of the known inanimate objects. Biological entities, of course, are subject to the laws of quantum physics and statistical mechanics. However, is modern physics enough to adequately describe the model and explain the evolution of biological complexity?

This article provides a detailed analysis of the analogies between statistical thermodynamics and the population-genetic theory of biological evolution. Based on the presented analogies, we outline new perspectives in relation to theoretical approaches in biology and major transitional periods of evolution, and also offer a biological equivalent of thermodynamic potential, which reflects the propensity for changes in the evolving population.

It is assumed that there are deep analogies: between the properties of biological entities and the processes in them on the one hand, and non-equilibrium states in physics, for objects such as glass. Such systems are characterized by a violation whereby a local state with a minimum of free energy conflicts with a global minimum, resulting in “nascent qualities”. We disseminate such analogies through the study of manifestations of nascent qualities, such as, for example, between different levels of selection in biological evolution. Such frustration effects appear as drivers in the evolution of biological complexity.

Next, we turn to evolution in multidimensional adaptive landscapes, considering them from the point of view of percolation theory (percolation), and assume that percolation at a level above the critical threshold causes a tree-like evolution of complex organisms. Taken together, these multiple connections between fundamental processes in physics and biology mean that the construction of a meaningful physical theory of biological evolution cannot be a futile attempt. However, it would not be realistic to expect such a theory to be created by “one scooping”; even if we move towards this, this can only happen through the integration of various physical models of evolutionary processes. Moreover, the existing framework of theoretical physics is unlikely to be satisfactory for adequate modeling of the biological level of complexity, and it is likely that new developments are needed in physics itself.

Introduction


What is the difference between living organisms and inanimate matter? There is an obvious answer to this question when defining in terms of chemical composition and structure. (At least, because the only suitable case, namely, life on Earth, refers to this). But when it comes to the basic processes of the evolution of life, the difference becomes less obvious. In the Darwinian tradition, it is tempting to argue that life is determined by evolution through the survival of the fittest [1–4].

However, the uniqueness of this process can be questioned, since the entire history of the Universe consists of changes that withstand the most stable (adapted) structures. Moreover, the process of replication (reproduction) is not in itself unique and exists not only in biology: crystals also replicate. On a macroscopic scale of time and space, however, life is undoubtedly a clear phenomenon. For an objective determination of the characteristic features by which life differs from other phenomena existing in the Universe, it is important to investigate key processes of biological evolution within the framework of theoretical physics [5, 6].

Perhaps the main feature that distinguishes modern physics from other areas of human exploratory activity is the obvious link between theory and experiment, in which research programs are formed by verifiable theoretical predictions. In a general sense, modern biology is not a science based on theory, in the sense in which physics is interpreted. But there is a significant exception, namely - population genetics (a formalized section of biology, which is effectively structured as a field of theoretical physics), similar mainly to statistical thermodynamics [7-10].

At the same time, mathematical models of population genetics are highly effective in immunology [11, 12] and biological oncology [13–16], which, perhaps, suggests that further penetration of theory into biology could turn out to be real and productive. Modern theoretical physics is an area with many strong links in which the most diverse subdivisions of physics are intertwined. At present, population genetics or some other direction of theoretical biology is not part of such a network. It is possible to argue that this separation is not optimal, since many sections of theoretical physics would provide information and stimulate theoretical developments in biology.

And yet there is still such a landmark question: is modern physics sufficiently filled to serve (provide support) for biology? A similar question, in various formulations (in particular, “whether biology is reducible to physics”), has a long and very dramatic history (for example, [17, 18]).

Without going into details of a historical or philosophical plan, we reject any assumption that life may follow some special laws of “biological” physics instead of the general ones that exist. For example, quantum mechanics, in general, is quite effective and applicable to living organisms, just like any other form of matter. The problem is that this strong theory, to a certain extent, can be considered as a “theory of everything”, as it introduces little in explaining biological phenomena [19, 20]. Of course, quantum-mechanical calculations can be useful in analyzing biochemical reactions, but they can not help us in understanding evolution. Therefore, it is assumed that the physical concept, which could be the main one in the theoretical description of biological phenomena, is the appearance (or emergence, emergency), that is, the collective behavior of large aggregates, which is qualitatively different from the behavior of their components. “More is different” is so anphoristically formulated by Anderson [19-24].

In his book containing fruitful ideas “What is life? The physical aspect of the living cell "Schrodinger made several basic points that even after 70 years remain at the heart of many discussions about the significance of physics for biology [25]. Probably the most significant is the characterization (at that time hypothetical) of molecular carriers of heredity as “aperiodic crystals”. Schrödinger was inaccurate in such a definition of an aperiodic crystal, and so far this metaphor covers the basic properties that were later discovered (not without the influence of Schrödinger) of biological information carriers, DNA and RNA [26-28].

Molecules of nucleic acids, in particular DNA, combine the uniformity (and periodicity) of the spatial structure with the effectiveness of multiple diversity (aperiodicity) of the main sequence. The combination of these distinctive features makes nucleic acids the only known molecules suitable for storing and transmitting digital information [29], in full accordance with Schrödinger's prediction. As for modern physics, biological “aperiodic crystals” are sometimes referred to as “glasses” [19, 20]. In fact, there are deep analogies, at various levels, between the state of glass and biological structures and the phenomena discussed below. At the same time, it will be shown that there are significant differences: in a certain sense, the glasses exhibit excessive confusion.

Another well-known statement by Schrödinger that organisms use “negative entropy” (or negentropy, a term that Schrödinger obviously liked but was not picked up by researchers) is potentially deceptive. Strikingly, during the time of Schrödinger, it seemed widespread, albeit uncertain, the view that such complex systems as living beings sometimes violate the second law of thermodynamics, and that such an apparent “violation” requires a special explanation [30].

Now we better understand the nature of entropy and the second law of thermodynamics, so that such a view of Schrödinger is possible and necessary to clarify. Obviously, the biosphere and the Earth as a whole are not closed systems, but rather open to a constant flow of energy, mostly from the Sun (other sources of relatively lesser environmental significance include the radioactive decay of heavy elements in the interior of the Earth).

Earthly life uses this flow of energy through photosynthesis, carried out by photo autotrophs (organisms that use light energy to biosynthesis of cell components), which function, to a certain extent, like photochemical machines. Of course, when considering the Sun-Earth system, even the appearance of a violation of the second law of thermodynamics is absent. Each individual organism, population, or ecosystem is also thermodynamically open systems. And more appropriate would be the statement that organisms mainly consume energy along with chemical building blocks, rather than 'negentropy', according to Schrödinger's bizarre statement.

However, with regard to Schrödinger's current motivation in the presentation of 'negentropy', it can be said that this correlates with some of the most fundamental and complex problems of biology, namely, the emergence and preservation of a surprising order and gigantic complexity in living organisms. Complexity is undoubtedly one of the most problematic concepts in all of science; it confronts all-encompassing definitions [34]. In fact, the most used definitions of complexity are context dependent. In biology, complexity is significant, at least at the level of genomes, organisms, and ecosystems [35, 36].

The complexity of the genome can be clearly interpreted through the number of nucleotide sites that are selected and thus carry biologically significant information [37-39], although the detailed definition does not take into account other important sources of complexity at the genome level, such as alternative transcription initiation and alternative splicing in eukaryotes (alternative splicing in eukaryotes). Complexity in relation to the organism and ecology is usually perceived as the number of individual constituent parts and / or hierarchy levels in the respective systems [40]. Regardless of the exact definitions, it seems clear that a consistently maintained, ever-increasing level of complexity is an exceptional characteristic feature of life and a major challenge for theoretical constructs.

The most traditional means of interaction between physics and biology is biophysics, which studies the properties of the structure and dynamics of biological macromolecules, as well as the structure of cells and organisms, together with their functions, through the approaches adopted in physics. Various areas of biophysics have proven to be productive and successful for several decades [41]. However, this is, after all, a separate additional area of ​​interaction between physics and biology, whereby physical theory is used to describe, model and analyze biological processes, in particular, evolution at the population level.

Already, Bohr attached particular importance (as part of the general discussion on the complementarity principle) of complementarity between the purely physical, structural approach to organisms and the “whole” nature as living beings [42]. The principle of drawing analogies between thermodynamics and statistical mechanics, on the one hand, and population genetics, on the other hand, was first proposed by the famous statistician and founder of the theory of population genetics, Ronald Fisher in the 1920s [43], and in subsequent years development of a theoretical approach to this process [7, 9, 10].

In various forms, theoretical formalism (mathematical models for describing a theory) from statistical mechanics was increasingly used to substantiate the model of biological evolution. Among other similar mathematical models, the use of percolation theory for analyzing evolution in adaptive landscapes [44-46] finds significant use. The main goal of such penetration of physics into evolutionary biology is rather ambitious: it is nothing more than the development of a physical theory of biological evolution, or even the transformation of biology into a part of physics [5, 6].

Obviously, such a comprehensive program, even a feasible in principle, cannot be implemented in one fell swoop. Only progress is possible at one of the stages at a given time by simulating a diverse evolutionary process using the ideas and mathematical apparatus of theoretical physics in the hope that in the end it will be possible to combine such models into a harmonious theoretical justification.

In this article, we discuss several aspects of biological evolution, where theoretical considerations, originating initially from condensed physical concepts, seem possible. We propose for consideration the statement that physical theory is capable of making a non-trivial contribution to the current understanding of evolution, and the latest theoretical developments in physics itself will probably be in demand with full consideration of the phenomenon of the emergence and evolution of the complexity level, which is characteristic of biological systems.

* The following sections of the article are summarized

Analogies in thermodynamics and population genetics and basic evolutionary transitions


Although the existence of analogies when comparing statistical mechanics and population genetics has already been noted by previous researchers, a detailed comparison was made in the paper by Sella and Hirsch, 2005 [7] with the subsequent development in the works of Barton and co-authors [9, 10] (Table 1).

Thus, evolutionary transitions are represented as analogues of adiabatic transitions of the first kind, while the density of evolutionary information and the evolutionary temperature (effective population size) are thermodynamically related variables.

Life, glass and patterns: frustrating systems and biological evolution


According to the first presented “theory of spin glasses” in the work of Edwards and Anderson [58], in modern physics it is believed that glass represents a certain state of matter, intermediate between the equilibrium and nonequilibrium [59-62].

A characteristic property of glass is aging, or structural relaxation. For example, suppose we define a specific characteristic in the equilibrium phase of a substance in a liquid or solid state, for example, the resistivity of a metal (or a liquid metal). The “equilibrium” state is characterized by the fact that during the subsequent measurement after the heating cycle (slow heating followed by cooling to the initial temperature) we obtain the same specific resistance value. For glass, it is possible to slowly change the measured value from measurement to measurement. The relief of potential energy (or landscape, when using the term in biological connotation) for glass is a function with many (asymptotic, infinite) local minima separated by barriers with an extremely wide distribution of energy. Each of the local minima is a metastable state. During the process of changing the thermal state, the system slowly moves from one minimum to another. It is important that the state of the glass is non-ergodic [59-62].

The state of the glass is characterized by the “order parameter” always with a set of components, denoted by real numbers x ∈ (0,1) [63]. Such a number can be represented as an infinite, non-periodic binary fraction, such as 0.10001110 ..., where 0 (1) corresponds to the choice of bifurcation on the relief of the complex energy, when cooled from a liquid equilibrium state. This process of changing the thermal state is usually described by the term ultra-metricity: in other words, we are mainly interested in the topological description of the evolution of the system through bifurcations, rather than the specific characteristics of barriers, the magnitude of transitions and other characteristics [60]. This feature is the main definition of the concept of an aperiodic Schrödinger crystal [25].

The main difference is that glasses are not only aperiodic, but also non-ergodic - a sign that causes an evolutionary process. The suitability of the glassy concept for biology is noted in Laughlin et al. [19,20]. At the same time, the defining signs of life, namely, replication with selection, seem to go beyond the behavior of ordinary glass: the potential relief for glass seems to be too flexible and characteristic for a certain kind of substances, which does not quite correspond to the model of biological evolution. Glass shows essentially infinite variability, whereas life is based on discrete forms, such as genomes with specific sequences and certain, long intervals of stability (see further discussion regarding evolutionary transitions).

* Translator's note

The following two sections of the article are not translated. Best of all, of course, read the original article. The author of the abridged translation suggests that this text may be of interest to readers as a popular science material.

Percolation + criticality: the basis and state of the tree-like evolutionary process
Mapping and separation of genotype-phenotype as a measurement


Concluding remarks


“The General Physical Theory of Biology” is probably an impossible dream, but it is indeed possible to describe key evolutionary processes in the language of statistical physics. It is already generally accepted that random (stochastic) processes play a significant role in evolution, and that fluctuations are the drivers of biological complexity, at least in part. Therefore, the use of statistical physics is natural. However, one should not go too far. Natural selection and adaptation are also essential factors of biological evolution, and for embedding these phenomena into the framework of physical theory, the existing apparatus of statistical physics probably requires clarification.

Here we tried to suggest what kind of modifications might be required for this. The arising phenomena, which are peculiar for theoretical modeling, glass and other condensed matter states are also central for biology. However, it seems that special principles not yet developed in statistical physics need to be created for the physical theory of separation of the genotype-phenotype and mapping, which embodies the basis of evolution.

Biological evolution in no way ignores the laws of physics, but the emerging biological phenomena initiate the further development of physics itself. Биологические существа и их эволюция не просто следуют принципу “more is different”, но и в некоторых отношениях, представляются качественно отличными от небиологических феноменов, указывающих на отдельные формы «феномена появления», что требует новой физической теории.

Различие между биологией и физикой (по крайней мере, известное нам) заключается не в том, что “ничто в биологии не имеет смысла кроме, как в свете эволюции” [3], тогда как в физике “все имеет смысл”. Последнее утверждение не представляется в действительности верным вне пределов квантовой физики, так как целую вселенную определенно возможно правильно воспринимать только в свете ее эволюции на протяжении 13,8 миллиардов лет.

Следуя выше указанной аналогии, в биологии, также как и в физике, выполнение измерений инициирует стрелу времени и создает необходимость признания эволюции. Однако, биологическая эволюция характеризуется существенными отличительными признаками, попытка охвата некоторых из которых была здесь нами предпринята, в частности, посредством применения концепций физики конденсированных сред, таких как фрустрация и перколяция (разрушение и просачивание), к центральным процессам биологической эволюции. Очевидно, анализ и обсуждение представленного здесь материала будут относиться только к предварительным рассуждениям для непрерывных, согласованных усилий, которые требуются для объединения биологии и физики.

Библиография
1. Darwin C: On the Origin of Species; 1859.
2. Dobzhansky T: Genetics and the origin of species, 2nd edn. New York: Columbia University Press; 1951.
3. Dobzhansky T: Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher 1973, 35, 125-129.
4. Koonin EV: The Logic of Chance: The Nature and Origin of Biological Evolution Upper Saddle River, NJ: FT press; 2011.
5. Wallace AR: On the tendency of species to form varieties; and on the perpetuation of varieties and species by natural mean of selection. III. On the tendency of varieties to depart indefinitely from the original type. J Proc Linn Soc London 1858, 3, 53-62.
6. Goldenfeld N, Woese C: Biology's next revolution. Nature 2007, 445(7126), 369.
7. Goldenfeld N, Woese CR: Life is Physics: Evolution as a Collective Phenomenon Far From Equilibrium. Annu Rev CondensMatter Phys 2011, 2, 375-399.
8. Sella G, Hirsh AE: The application of statistical physics to evolutionary biology. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2005, 102(27), 9541-9546.
9. Ao P: Emerging of Stochastic Dynamical Equalities and Steady State Thermodynamics from Darwinian Dynamics. Commun Theor Phys 2008, 49(5), 1073-1090.
10. Barton NH, Coe JB: On the application of statistical physics to evolutionary biology. J Theor Biol 2009, 259(2), 317-324.
11. de Vladar HP, Barton NH: The contribution of statistical physics to evolutionary biology. Trends Ecol Evol 2011, 26(8), 424-432.
12. Barreiro LB, Quintana-Murci L: From evolutionary genetics to human immunology: how selection shapes host defence genes. Nat Rev Genet 2010, 11(1), 17-30.
13. Seppala O: Natural selection on quantitative immune defence traits: a comparison between theory and data. J Evol Biol 2015, 28(1), 1-9.
14. Bozic I, Antal T, Ohtsuki H, Carter H, Kim D, Chen S, Karchin R, Kinzler KW, Vogelstein B, Nowak MA: Accumulation of driver and passenger mutations during tumor progression. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2010, 107(43), 18545-18550.
15. Casas-Selves M, Degregori J: How cancer shapes evolution, and how evolution shapes cancer. Evolution (NY) 2011, 4(4), 624-634.
16. McFarland CD, Korolev KS, Kryukov GV, Sunyaev SR, Mirny LA: Impact of deleterious passenger mutations on cancer progression. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2013, 110(8), 2910-2915.
17. McFarland CD, Mirny LA, Korolev KS: Tug-of-war between driver and passenger mutations in cancer and other adaptive processes. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2014, 111(42), 15138-15143.
18. Polanyi M: Life's irreducible structure. Science 1968, 160, 1308-1312.
19. Rosenberg A: Darwininan Reductionism, Or, How to Stop Worrying and Love MoOlecular Biology Chicago: Univ Chicago Press; 2006.
20. Laughlin RB, Pines D: The theory of everything. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2000, 97(1), 28-31.
21. Laughlin RB, Pines D, Schmalian J, Stojkovic BP, Wolynes P: The middle way. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2000, 97(1), 32-37.
22. Anderson PW: More is different. Science 1972, 177(4047), 393-396.
23. Laughlin RB: A Different Universe: Reinventing Physics From the Bottom Down. New York: Basic Books; 2008.
24. Anderson PW: More and Different: Notes from a Thoughtful Curmudgeon. Singapour: World Scientific Publishing Company; 2011.
25. West G: Scale: The Universal Laws of Growth, Innovation, Sustainability, and the Pace of Life in Organisms, Cities, Economies, and Companies. New York: Penguin Press; 2017.
26. Gell-Mann M: The Quark and the Jaguar: Adventures in the Simple and the Complex New York: St. Martin's Griffin; 1995.
27. Adami C, Ofria C, Collier TC: Evolution of biological complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2000, 97(9), 4463-4468.
28. McShea DW, Brandon RN: Biology's First Law: The Tendency for Diversity and Complexity to Increase in Evolutionary Systems. Chicago: Univ Chicago Press; 2010.
29. Adami C: What is complexity? Bioessays 2002, 24(12), 1085-1094.
30. Koonin EV: A non-adaptationist perspective on evolution of genomic complexity or the continued dethroning of man. Cell Cycle 2004, 3(3), 280-285.
31. Koonin EV: The meaning of biological information. Philos Trans A Math Phys Eng Sci 2016, 374(2063).
32. Heim NA, Payne JL, Finnegan S, Knope ML, Kowalewski M, Lyons SK, McShea DW, Novack-Gottshall PM, Smith FA, Wang SC: Hierarchical complexity and the size limits of life. Proc Biol Sci 2017, 284(1857).
33. Egelman E (ed.): Comprehensive Biophysics. New York: Academic Press; 2012.
34. Fisher RA: The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. London & New York: Oxford University Press; 1930.
35. Gavrilets S: Fitness Landscapes and the Origin of Species. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2004.
36. Gavrilets S, Gravner J: Percolation on the fitness hypercube and the evolution of reproductive isolation. J Theor Biol 1997, 184(1), 51-64.
37. Gravner J, Pitman D, Gavrilets S: Percolation on fitness landscapes: effects of correlation, phenotype, and incompatibilities. J Theor Biol 2007, 248(4), 627-645.
38. Shannon CE, Weaver W: The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Chicago: University of Illinois Press; 1949.
39. Lynch M: The origins of genome archiecture. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates; 2007.
40. Lynch M, Conery JS: The origins of genome complexity. Science 2003, 302(5649), 1401-1404.
41. Lynch M: The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2007, 104 Suppl 1, 8597-8604.
42. Lynch M: The origins of eukaryotic gene structure. Mol Biol Evol 2006, 23(2), 450-468.
43. Koonin EV: Evolution of genome architecture. Int J Biochem Cell Biol 2009, 41(2), 298-306.
44. Maynard Smith J, Szathmary E: The Major Transitions in Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1997.
45. Szathmary E: Toward major evolutionary transitions theory 2.0. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2015, 112(33), 10104-10111.
46. Landau LD, Lifshitz EM: Statistical Physics. Oxford: Pergamon; 1980.
47. Bloch I, Dalibard J, Zwerger W: Many-body physics with ultracold gases. Reviews of Modern Physics 2008, 80(3), 885-964.
48. Lewenstein M, Sanpera A, Ahufinger V: Ultracold Atoms in Optical Lattices: Simulating Quantum Many-Body Systems. Oxford: Oxford Univ Press; 2012.
49. Edwards SF, Anderson PW: Theory of spin glasses. J Phys F: Metal Phys 1975, 5, 965-974.
50. Mezard M, Parisi G, Virasoro MA (eds.): Spin Glass Theory and Beyond Singapore: World Scientific; 1987.
51. Rammal R, Toulouse G, Virasoro MA: Ultrametricity for physicists. Rev Mod Phys 1986, 58, 765-788.
52. Binder K, Young AP: Spin glasses: Experimental facts, theoretical concepts, and open questions. Rev Mod Phys 58, 801-976 1986, 58, 801-976.
53. Das SP: Mode-coupling theory and the glass transition in supercooled liquids. Rev Mod Phys 76, 785-851 2004, 76, 785-851.
54. Parisi G: A sequence of approximated solutions to the SK model for spin glasses. J Phys A 1980, 13, 1101-1112.
55. Schroedinger E: What is Life? The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell. Dublin: Trinity College Press; 1944.
56. Monasson R: Structural Glass Transition and the Entropy of the Metastable States. Phys Rev Lett 1995, 75, 2847-2850.
57. Schmalian G, Wolynes PG: Stripe Glasses: Self-Generated Randomness in a Uniformly Frustrated System. Phys Rev Lett 85, 836-839 2000, 85, 836-839.
58. Principi A, Katsnelson MI: Stripe glasses in ferromagnetic thin films. Phys Rev B 93 2016, 93, 054410.
59. Principi A, Katsnelson MI: Self-Induced Glassiness and Pattern Formation in Spin Systems Subject to Long-Range Interactions. Phys Rev Lett 117 2016, 117, 137201
60. Ruelle D: Statistical Mechanics: Rigorous Results Singapore: World Scientific; 1999.
61. Villain J, Bidaux R, Carton JP, Conte R: Order as an effect of disorder. J Phys France 1980, 41, 1263-1272.
62. Shender EF: Antiferromagnetic garnets with fluctuationally interacting sublattices. Sov Phys JETP 1982, 56, 178-184.
63. Henley CL: Ordering due to disorder in a frustrated vector antiferromagnet. Phys Rev Lett 1989, 62, 2056-2059.
64. Forterre P, Prangishvili D: The great billion-year war between ribosome- and capsid-encoding organisms (cells and viruses) as the major source of evolutionary novelties. Ann NY Acad Sci 2009, 1178, 65-77.
65. Aravind L, Anantharaman V, Zhang D, de Souza RF, Iyer LM: Gene flow and biological conflict systems in the origin and evolution of eukaryotes. Front Cell Infect Microbiol 2012, 2, 89.
66. Stern A, Sorek R: The phage-host arms race: shaping the evolution of microbes. Bioessays 2011, 33(1), 43-51.
67. Koonin EV, Krupovic M: A Movable Defense. The Scientist 2015(january 1).
68. Jalasvuori M, Koonin EV: Classification of prokaryotic genetic replicators: between selfishness and altruism. Ann NY Acad Sci 2015, 1341, 96-105.
69. Koonin EV, Starokadomskyy P: Are viruses alive? The replicator paradigm sheds decisive light on an old but misguided question. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 2016, 59, 125-134.
70. Holmes EC: The Evolution and Emergence of RNA Viruses. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2009.
71. Koonin EV, Wolf YI, Katsnelson MI: Inevitability of the emergence and persistence of genetic parasites caused by thermodynamic instability of parasite-free states. Biol Direct 2017 12(1):31.
72. Koonin EV: Viruses and mobile elements as drivers of evolutionary transitions. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 2016, 371(1701).
73. Szathmary E: The evolution of replicators. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 2000, 355(1403), 1669-1676.
74. Takeuchi N, Hogeweg P: Evolution of complexity in RNA-like replicator systems. Biol Direct 2008, 3, 11.
75. Takeuchi N, Hogeweg P: Evolutionary dynamics of RNA-like replicator systems: A bioinformatic approach to the origin of life. Phys Life Rev 2012, 9(3), 219-263.
76. Takeuchi N, Hogeweg P, Koonin EV: On the origin of DNA genomes: Evolution of the division of labor between template and catalyst in model replicator systems PLoS Comput Biol 2011, in press.
77. Labrie SJ, Samson JE, Moineau S: Bacteriophage resistance mechanisms. Nat Rev Microbiol 2010, 8, 317-327.
78. Makarova KS, Wolf YI, Koonin EV: Comparative genomics of defense systems in archaea and bacteria. Nucleic Acids Res 2013, 41(8), 4360-4377.
79. Koonin EV, Makarova KS, Wolf YI: Evolutionary Genomics of Defense Systems in Archaea and Bacteria. Annu Rev Microbiol 2017.
80. Ameisen JC: On the origin, evolution, and nature of programmed cell death: a timeline of four billion years. Cell Death Differ 2002, 9(4), 367-393.
81. Koonin EV, Aravind L: Origin and evolution of eukaryotic apoptosis: the bacterial connection. Cell Death Differ 2002, 9(4), 394-404.
82. Ameisen JC: Looking for death at the core of life in the light of evolution. Cell Death Differ 2004, 11(1), 4-10.
83. Kaczanowski S: Apoptosis: its origin, history, maintenance and the medical implications for cancer and aging. Phys Biol 2016, 13(3), 031001.
84. Koonin EV, Zhang F: Coupling immunity and programmed cell suicide in prokaryotes: Life-or-death choices. Bioessays 2017, 39(1), 1-9.
85. Iranzo J, Lobkovsky AE, Wolf YI, Koonin EV: Virus-host arms race at the joint origin of multicellularity and programmed cell death. Cell Cycle 2014, 13(19), 3083-3088.
86. Durand PM, Sym S, Michod RE: Programmed Cell Death and Complexity in Microbial Systems. Curr Biol 2016, 26(13), R587-593.
87. Embley TM, Martin W: Eukaryotic evolution, changes and challenges. Nature 2006, 440(7084), 623-630.
88. Embley TM, Williams TA: Evolution: Steps on the road to eukaryotes. Nature 2015, 521(7551), 169-170.
89. Martin W, Koonin EV: Introns and the origin of nucleus-cytosol compartmentation. Nature 2006, 440, 41-45.
90. Spang A, Saw JH, Jorgensen SL, Zaremba-Niedzwiedzka K, Martijn J, Lind AE, van Eijk R, Schleper C, Guy L, Ettema TJ: Complex archaea that bridge the gap between prokaryotes and eukaryotes. Nature 2015, 521(7551), 173-179.
91. Koonin EV: Origin of eukaryotes from within archaea, archaeal eukaryome and bursts of gene gain: eukaryogenesis just made easier? Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 2015, 370(1678), 20140333.
92. Koonin EV: Archaeal ancestors of eukaryotes: not so elusive any more. BMC Biol 2015, 13, 84.
93. Zaremba-Niedzwiedzka K, Caceres EF, Saw JH, Backstrom D, Juzokaite L, Vancaester E, Seitz KW, Anantharaman K, Starnawski P, Kjeldsen KU et al: Asgard archaea illuminate the origin of eukaryotic cellular complexity. Nature 2017, 541(7637), 353-358.
94. Lopez-Garcia P, Moreira D: Selective forces for the origin of the eukaryotic nucleus. Bioessays 2006, 28(5), 525-533.
95. Koonin EV: The origin of introns and their role in eukaryogenesis: a compromise solution to the introns-early versus introns-late debate? Biol Direct 2006, 1, 22.
96. Koonin EV: Intron-dominated genomes of early ancestors of eukaryotes. J Hered 2009, 100(5), 618-623.
97. Blackstone NW: Why did eukaryotes evolve only once? Genetic and energetic aspects of conflict and conflict mediation. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 2013, 368(1622), 20120266.
98. Suomalainen A, Battersby BJ: Mitochondrial diseases: the contribution of organelle stress responses to pathology. Nat Rev Mol Cell Biol 2017.
99. Bensasson D, Zhang D, Hartl DL, Hewitt GM: Mitochondrial pseudogenes: evolution's misplaced witnesses. Trends Ecol Evol 2001, 16(6), 314-321.
100. Michod RE: Evolution of individuality during the transition from unicellular to multicellular life. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2007, 104 Suppl 1, 8613-8618.
101. Leslie MP, Shelton DE, Michod RE: Generation time and fitness tradeoffs during the evolution of multicellularity. J Theor Biol 2017, 430, 92-102.
102. Aktipis CA, Boddy AM, Jansen G, Hibner U, Hochberg ME, Maley CC, Wilkinson GS: Cancer across the tree of life: cooperation and cheating in multicellularity. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 2015, 370(1673).
103. Greaves M: Evolutionary determinants of cancer. Cancer Discov 2015, 5(8), 806-820.
104. Jacqueline C, Biro PA, Beckmann C, Moller AP, Renaud F, Sorci G, Tasiemski A, Ujvari B, Thomas F: Cancer: A disease at the crossroads of trade-offs. Evol Appl 2017, 10(3), 215-225.
105. Archetti M: Complementation, genetic conflict, and the evolution of sex and recombination. J Hered 2010, 101 Suppl 1, S21-33.
106. Gavrilets S: Is sexual conflict an «engine of speciation»? Cold Spring Harb Perspect Biol 2014, 6(12), a017723.
107. Nonacs P: Kinship, greenbeards, and runaway social selection in the evolution of social insect cooperation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2011, 108 Suppl 2, 10808-10815.
108. de Gennes PG: Scaling Concepts in Polymer Physics Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press 1979.
109. Shklovskii BI, Efros AL: Electronic Properties of Doped Semiconductors Berlin.: Springer; 1984.
110. Mustonen V, Lassig M: From fitness landscapes to seascapes: non-equilibrium dynamics of selection and adaptation. Trends Genet 2009, 25(3), 111-119.
111. Catalan P, Arias CF, Cuesta JA, Manrubia S: Adaptive multiscapes: an up-to-date metaphor to visualize molecular adaptation. Biol Direct 2017, 12(1), 7.
112. Haldane JBS: The cost of natural selection. J Genet 1957, 55, 511-524.
113. Darlington PJ, Jr.: The cost of evolution and the imprecision of adaptation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1977, 74(4), 1647-1651.
114. Darlington PJ, Jr.: Evolution: questions for the modern theory. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1983, 80(7), 1960-1963.
115. Barton NH: Linkage and the limits to natural selection. Genetics 1995, 140(2), 821-841.
116. Bell G: Evolutionary rescue and the limits of adaptation. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 2013, 368(1610), 20120080.
117. Smirnov S: Critical percolation in the plane: conformal invariance, Cardy's formula, scaling limits. CR Acad Sci Paris Sér I Math 2001, 333, 239-244.
118. Beffara V: Hausdorff dimensions for SLE6. Ann Probab 2004., 32, 2606-2629.
119. Kager W, Nienhuis B: A Guide to Stochastic Löwner Evolution and Its Applications. J Stat Phys 2004, 115, 1149-1229.
120. Aizenman M, Newman CM: Tree graph inequalities and critical behavior in percolation models
J Stat Phys 1984 36, 107-143.
121. Barsky DJ, Aizenman M: Percolation Critical Exponents Under the Triangle Condition Ann Prob 1991 19, 1520-1536.
122. Hara T, Slade G: Mean-field critical behaviour for percolation in high dimensions. Commun Math Phys 1990, 128, 333-391.
123. Puigbo P, Wolf YI, Koonin EV: Search for a 'Tree of Life' in the thicket of the phylogenetic forest. J Biol 2009, 8(6), 59.
124. Puigbo P, Wolf YI, Koonin EV: Seeing the Tree of Life behind the phylogenetic forest. BMC Biol 2013, 11, 46.
125. Puigbo P, Wolf YI, Koonin EV: The tree and net components of prokaryote evolution. Genome Biol Evol 2010, 2, 745-756.
126. Doolittle WF: Lateral genomics. Trends Cell Biol 1999, 9(12), M5-8.
127. Doolittle WF: Phylogenetic classification and the universal tree. Science 1999, 284(5423), 2124-2129.
128. Doolittle WF: Uprooting the tree of life. Sci Am 2000, 282(2), 90-95.
129. Doolittle WF, Bapteste E: Pattern pluralism and the Tree of Life hypothesis. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2007, 104(7), 2043-2049.
130. Bapteste E, Susko E, Leigh J, MacLeod D, Charlebois RL, Doolittle WF: Do orthologous gene phylogenies really support tree-thinking? BMC Evol Biol 2005, 5, 33.
131. Koonin EV, Dolja VV, Krupovic M: Origins and evolution of viruses of eukaryotes: The ultimate modularity. Virology 2015, 479-480, 2-25.
132. Iranzo J, Krupovic M, Koonin EV: The Double-Stranded DNA Virosphere as a Modular Hierarchical Network of Gene Sharing. MBio 2016, 7(4).
133. Iranzo J, Krupovic M, Koonin EV: A network perspective on the virus world. Commun Integr Biol 2017, 10(2), e1296614.
134. Pattee HH: The physics of symbols: bridging the epistemic cut. Biosystems 2001, 60(1-3), 5-21.
135. Koonin EV: Why the Central Dogma: on the nature of the great biological exclusion principle. Biol Direct 2015, 10, 52.
136. von Neumann J: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press; 1955.
137. Heisenberg W: The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory New York: Dover 1949
138. Jammer M: The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics New York: McGraw-Hill; 1966
139. Wheeler JA, Zurek WH (eds.): Quantum Theory and Measurements. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press; 1983
140. Ballintine LE: Quantum Mechanics: a Modern Development. Singapore: World Scientific; 2003
141. Bohr N: The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, vol. 4. Oxford: Ox Bow Press; 1987.
142. Giulini D, Joos E, Kiefer C, Kupsch J, Stamatescu IO, Zeh HD: Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory Berlin: Springer; 1996.
143. Zurek WH: Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical. Rev Mod Phys 2003 75, 715-775.
144. Allaverdyan AE, Ballian R, Nieuwenhuizen TM: Understanding quantum measurement from the solution of dynamical models. Phys Rep 2013 525 1-166.
145. De Raedt H, Katsnelson MI, Michielsen K: Quantum theory as the most robust description of reproducible experiments. Ann Phys 2014, 347, 45-73.
146. De Raedt H, Katsnelson MI, Michielsen K: Quantum theory as plausible reasoning applied to data obtained by robust experiments. Phil Trans Royal Soc A 2016, 374, 20150233
147. Pattee HH: Quantum mechanics, heredity and the origin of life. J Theor Biol 1967, 17(3), 410-420.
148. Frank SA: Natural selection. V. How to read the fundamental equations of evolutionary change in terms of information theory. J Evol Biol 2012, 25(12), 2377-2396.
149. Muller HJ: The Relation of Recombination to Mutational Advance. Mutat Res 1964, 106, 2-9.
150. Haigh J: The accumulation of deleterious genes in a population--Muller's Ratchet. Theor Popul Biol 1978, 14(2), 251-267.
151. Lynch M, Gabriel W: Mutation Load and the Survival of Small Populations. Evolution 1990, 44(7), 1725-1737.
152. Redfield RJ: Evolution of bacterial transformation: is sex with dead cells ever better than no sex at all? Genetics 1988, 119(1), 213-221.
153. Iranzo J, Puigbo P, Lobkovsky AE, Wolf YI, Koonin EV: Inevitability of Genetic Parasites. Genome Biol Evol 2016, 8(9), 2856-2869.
154. Takeuchi N, Kaneko K, Koonin EV: Horizontal gene transfer can rescue prokaryotes from Muller's ratchet: benefit of DNA from dead cells and population subdivision. G3 (Bethesda) 2014, 4(2), 325-339.
155. Feynman RP, Hibbs AR: Quantum Mechanics and Path Integrals. New York: McGraw Hill; 1965
156. Bennett CH: Demons, engines, and the Second Law. Sci Am 1987, 257, 108-117.
157. Bennett CH: Notes on Landauer's principle, reversible computation, and Maxwell's Demon. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 2003, 34, 501-510.
158. Landauer R: Irreversibility and Heat Generation in the Computing Process. IBM Journal of Research and Development 1961, 5, 183-191.

Кросспост

Source: https://habr.com/ru/post/438900/